In this
post I want to introduce the idea of a higher-order modal logic—not
a modal logic for higher-order predicate logic, but rather a logic of
higher-order modalities. “What is a higher-order modality?”, you
might be wondering. Well, if a first-order modality is a way that some
entity could have been—whether it is a mereological atom, or a
mereological complex, or the universe as a whole—a higher-order
modality is a way that a first-order modality could have been.
First-order modality is modeled in term of a space of possible
worlds—a set of worlds structured by an accessibility relation,
i.e., a relation of relative possibility—each world representing a
way that the entire universe could have been. A second-order modality
would be modeled in terms of a space of spaces of (first-order)
possible worlds, each space representing a way that the entire space
of (first-order) possible worlds could have been. And just as there
is a unique actual world which represents the way things really are,
there is a unique actual space
which represents the way that first-order
modality actually is.
Why,
though, should we adopt a framework like this? To
motivate it, consider the fact that people have mutually conflicting
intuitions about what the
space of all (first-order) possible worlds is like. Does
God exist in all, none, or only some worlds? Or
consider the famous dispute between Platonists and nominalists
concerning predication. Platonists
think that at least some predications can be true only if objects
exemplify properties, and nominalists deny this. They
think that there are no properties, but that predications can still
be true. For the one party, some predications essentially
involve properties, and for the other none do. Platonism, if true, is
necessarily true, and if false, is necessarily false. The
same goes for nominalism. Either
some predications essentially involve properties or none do. On
the face of it, this is problematic for the view that conceivability
implies possibility: Platonism and nominalism have both been
believed, and by many very able philosophers at that. What is
believed is conceivable in some sense, otherwise such “beliefs”
would have no content. So both positions are conceivable, but only
one is possible. Either way,
conceivability doesn't imply possibility.
But
maybe that's not quite true.
Perhaps, though only one of these positions is actually true, and
hence first-order possible, both views are second-order
possible. So
maybe conceivability does
imply possibility—at
some order or other. Related
considerations might apply to semantic content and possibility: If we
can coherently mean something, it can be the case—at some order or
other.
And
what is the accessibility
relation itself like?
Presumably it is reflexive, but
is it also symmetric, or transitive? And
whichever of these properties it may or may not have, could
that itself have been different? Could at least some rival modal
logics represent ways that first-order modality could have been?
To
be clear, the claim is not
just that some things which are possible or necessary might not have
been so, but rather that the
nature or structure of actual modality could have been different.
Even if the accessibility
relation is actually both symmetric and transitive, maybe
it could have (second-order) been otherwise: There
is a (second-order) possible space
of worlds in which it is different, where it fails to be symmetric,
or transitive. We must,
therefore, introduce the notion of a higher-order
accessibility relation, one that in this case relates spaces
of first-order worlds. The question then
arises as to whether that
relation is symmetric, or transitive. We can then consider
third-order modalities, spaces of spaces of spaces of possible worlds, where
the second-order accessibility relation differs from how it actually
is. I can see no reason why
there should be a limit to this hierarchy of
higher-order modalities, any
more than I can see a reason why there should be a limit to the
hierarchy of higher-order
properties.
The
accessibility relation is not the only thing that might be
thought to vary between spaces of worlds: Perhaps the contents of the
spaces can vary as well. While I presume that the contents of the
worlds themselves remain constant—it makes doubtful
sense to suppose that in one space an object o exists in w_1 and in
another space o doesn't exist in w_1—we
may suppose that the spaces differ as to which worlds they
contain. Thus we
might have a higher-order analogue of a variable-domain modal logic.
I
do not expect this kind of framework to settle the issue of how
modality at any order actually is—no more than I expect ordinary
first-order modal logic to
settle (aside from first-order necessary truths) what
is actually the case. What
goes for the actual world goes for the actual space of worlds, and
for all higher-order spaces of spaces. What
I do hope for is that it will, if it proves to be coherent, help
to clarify the terms of the
debate about the way modality is—to help us to state the issues,
and to see their interrelations, as clearly as we can.
I
think that's enough for this time. I'll leave the further
development of
such a framework for another occasion--or occasions—provided that
you, my readers, think it merits further development.
No comments:
Post a Comment